• Back to Profile

  • When one particular species of event has always … been conjoined with another,
    we make no longer any scruple of foretelling one upon the appearance of the other,
    and of employing that reasoning, which can alone assure us of any matter of fact or existence.
    We then call the one object, Cause; the other, Effect.
    - David Hume's (1748, §7) An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding

    Theories of Causation




    Hume's Criteria


    Hume's fork



    EVENT 1: Billiard ball 1 strikes billiard ball 2.
    EVENT 2:Billiard ball 2 moves.
    EVENT 1 causes EVENT 2


    1. Hume's argument:
    2. P1: All the objects of human reason or enquiry can be divided into 2 CATEGORIES: relations of ideas (CATEGORY 1) and matters of fact (CATEGORY 2).
    3. P2: There is a causal relationship between EVENT 1 and EVENT 2.
    4. P3: This causal relationship is an object of human reason or enquiry.
    5. P4: This causal relationship is not a relation of ideas (CATEGORY 1).
    6. C: ∴ This causal relationship is a matter of fact (CATEGORY 2).


    7. Matters of fact are known a posteriori from impressions rather than ideas

    8. Our impressions may be:
      1. External impressions — through our use of our traditional five senses; or
      2. Internal impressions — through custom or habit of mind






    David Hume




    According to our external impressions:
    1. The effect temporally follows from the cause (temporal succession)
    2. Cause and effect are spatiotemporally contiguous or close to each other (continguity)
    3. Causes are regularly followed by effects (constant conjunction)

    According to our internal impressions:
    1. We get into the habit of mind of expecting an effect after observing cause
    2. Custom or habit of mind is the source of our belief that:
      1. i) The future will be like the past
      2. ii) There is a necessary connection between causes and effects






    Hume's account of causal inference:
    1. STEP 1: From our external impressions, we have observed regularities between EVENT 1 and EVENT 2 (i.e. sufficiently many EVENT 1-tokens followed by EVENT 2-tokens) in the past
    2. STEP 2: From our internal impressions, we form the idea of a necessary connection between EVENT 1 and EVENT 2
    3. STEP 3: On observing EVENT 1 (cause), we make the causal inference that EVENT 2 (effect) will follow


    ∴ Hume's criteria for the concept of causality:
    1. CRITERION 1 (Contiguity) — A cause and its effect must be nearby each other in time and space
    2. CRITERION 2 (Temporal Priority) — A cause must precede its effect in time
    3. CRITERION 3 (Necessary Connection) — The cause always produces the effect and the effect is not produced without the cause

    4. NOTE:
    5. In the empirical definition, CRITERION 3 (Necessary connection) is replaced with CRITERION 3 (Constant Conjunction)
    6. CRITERION 3 (Constant Conjunction) — A cause is regularly followed by (i.e. conjoined with) its effect


    Regularity Theory of Causation



    J. S. Mill


    A. B. Hill


    J. L. Mackie




    1. According to the regularity theory of causation (Hume, 1748, Mill, 1843, Koch, 1932, Hill, 1965, Susser, 1973, Mackie, 1974, Naranjo et al, 1981):
    2. C causes E if every event of type C is followed by an event of type E

      1. X1 causes Y1 at token level
      2. X2 causes Y2 at token level
      3. X3 causes Y3 at token level
      4.   ⋮
    1. ∴ X causes Y at type level


    Hume (1748) reduced the inference of causal relationships to the identification of regularities

    According to Mackie's (1974) cause-as-INUS-condition account:
    1. A cause is an INUS (viz. insufficient but non-redundant part of an unnecessary but sufficient) condition

    2. C is an INUS condition of E iff:
      1. (C ∧ X) is sufficient for E;
      2. (C ∧ X) is not necessary, since Y could also cause E;
      3. C alone may be insufficient for E;
      4. C is a non-redundant part of (C ∧ X)

    1. C is a cause of E on a particular occasion (this is known as token or singular causality) iff:
    2. C is at least an INUS condition of E;
    3. C is present;
    4. The components of X (if there are any) were present;
    5. Every disjunct in Y not containing C as a conjunct was absent


    INUS analysis (Mackie, 1974)

    1. C — A lit match (present)
    2. X — Oxygen, flammable material, other conditions needed for a lit match to cause a fire
    3. Y — Lightning strike, faulty electrical wiring, other factors that cause fires in the absence of lit matches
    4. E — House in fire


    5. ((C ∧ X) ∨ Y) ⟷ E
    6. TRANSLATION: ((C ∧ X) ∨ Y) is necessary and sufficient for E


    7. Analysis:
    8. A lit match (C) may be the cause of the house fire
    9. However, if conditions needed for a lit match to cause a fire are absent (∼X), then C may not cause the fire
    10. In addition, there are some circumstances (Y) in which a fire occurs without C



    PROBLEMS with the regularity theory of causation


    Problem

    Description



    PROBLEM 1: Observed regularities are not sufficient




    X (common cause) causes both Y and Z
    ∴ Y, although a leading indicator of Z, would have a spurious (noncausal) correlation with Z


    Noncausal regularity between day and night (Reid, 1785)

    1. X: The spinning of the earth around its own axis
    2. Y: Day
    3. Z: Night

    4. There is a noncausal regularity between day and night
    5. ∴ Observed regularities are not sufficient for us to recognize relationships as causal relationships




    PROBLEM 2: Observed regularities are not necessary




    Certain causal relata are one-off: the Big Bang is a one-off cause, the murder of a specific individual is a one-off effect, etc
    ∴ Observed regularities are not necessary for us to recognize relationships as causal relationships

    In addition, some causal relationships are anomalous: a drug that normally cures a disease could cause death in a small fraction of the patient population that takes the drug




    PROBLEM 3: Specific challenges to each of Hume's criteria



    OBJECTIONS to CRITERION 1 (Contiguity):
    1. OBJECTION 1: The absence of an event (rather than the presence of it) can lead to an effect
    2. OBJECTION 2: An event could occur in one part of the world and cause an event elsewhere at a later time




    OBJECTIONS to CRITERION 2 (Temporal Priority):
    1. OBJECTION 1: There is simultaneous causal influence in physics




    OBJECTIONS to CRITERION 3 (Necessary Connection):
    1. OBJECTION 1: When there are multiple causes of an effect, each cause is no longer individually necessary




    PROBLEM 4: Selection problem



    There is no method for distinguishing between causally relevant parts of a regular sequence of events and causally irrelevant parts (e.g. mere background conditions, spurious correlations, etc)



    PROBLEM 5: No guidelines for establishing degree of causal influence




    Any event that has a small influence on the timing or manner of the effect can be said to be a cause
    However, there is no discussion in the regularity theory of causation of the degree to which a cause influences an effect




    Counterfactual Theory of Causation



    David Lewis


    Murali Ramachandran



    Hume's (1748, §7) An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding:
    '[W]e may define a cause to be an object followed by another, and where all the objects, similar to the first, are followed by objects similar to the second. Or, in other words where, if the first object had not been, the second never had existed'

    Hume offers two competing definitions of causality:
    1. Def 1 — for the regularity theory of causation
    2. Def 2 — for the counterfactual theory of causation


    1. According to the counterfactual theory of causation (Lewis, 1973, 1986, 2000, Ganeri, Noordhof & Ramachandran, 1996, Ramachandran, 1997):
    2. C causes E iff:
      1. E is causally dependent on C; or
      2. There is a chain of causal dependence between C and E


    STEP 1 (Lewis): Analysis of the truth conditions of counterfactuals in terms of possible and actual worlds (@, w1, w2, etc)




    1. X ☐⟶ Y — If X were true, then Y would be true

    2. 'X ☐⟶ Y' is true in the actual world @ iff:
    3. i) There are no possible worlds in which X is true (i.e. 'X ☐⟶ Y' would be vacuously true);
    4. ii) A possible world w1 in which both X and Y are true is closer to the actual world @ than any other possible world (w2, w3, etc) in which X is true and Y is false (i.e. 'X ☐⟶ Y' would be non-vacuously true);
    5. iii) Both X and Y are true in the actual world @ (a special case of (ii))




    STEP 2 (Lewis): Analysis of counterfactual dependence in terms of counterfactuals
    1. To say that 'X ☐⟶ Y' is true is to that Y depends counterfactually on X


    STEP 3 (Lewis): Analysis of causal dependence in terms of counterfactual dependence
    The general intuition is that counterfactual dependence captures something deep and essential about causality

    Causal dependence is represented in terms of counterfactuals:
    1. C ☐⟶ E — If C had occurred, then E would have occurred too
    2. ∼C ☐⟶ ∼E — If C had not occurred, then E would not have occurred too

    Had Homer Simpson not eaten so many doughnuts, he would not have gotten this plump


    STEP 4 (Lewis): Analysis of causation in terms of causal dependence
    Lewis's (1973, p. 200) 'Causation':
    'Causal dependence among actual events implies causation. If c and e are two actual events such that e would not have occurred without c, then c is a cause of e. But I reject the converse. Causation must always be transitive; causal dependence may not be; so there can be causation without causal dependence.'

    EXAMPLE: Causation without causal dependence


    There is a causal relationship between X and Z

    1. In the actual world @:
    2. If Z causally depends on Y, then Y causes Z
    3. If Y causally depends on X, then X causes Y
    4. X causes Y and Y causes Z
    5. There is a chain of causal dependence between X and Z
    6. ∴ By the transitivity of causation, X causes Z

    7. However, Z does not causally depend on X
    8. In possible world w1, Z depends causally and counterfactually on W
    9. ∴ There can be causation without causal dependence



    PROBLEMS with the counterfactual theory of causation


    Problem

    Description



    PROBLEM 1: Transitivity




    EXAMPLE:
    1. I give Jones a chest massage (C), without which he would have died
    2. Jones recovers and flies to New York (F), where he eventually has a violent death (D)
    3. C is the cause of F
    4. F is the cause of D
    5. However, C is not the cause of D: whether or not C occurred, Jones would still have died




    PROBLEM 2: Redundant causation




    1. C causes E in the actual world @
    2. However, it is not true that if C had not occurred, then E would not have occurred

    3. C and D are independent: neither C nor D cause the other
    4. If C had not occurred, then D would still have caused E: D is causally sufficient on its own
    5. If D had not occurred, then C would still have caused E: C is causally sufficient on its own
    6. ∴ While C causes E, had C not occurred, E would still have occurred (otherwise caused by D)


    EXAMPLE 1 (Redundant Causation): A firing squad



    EXAMPLE 2 (Redundant Causation): David Beckham and Ryan Giggs taking a free kick together (Aston Villa v. Man Utd in Aug 2001)


    EXAMPLE 3 (Redundant Causation): Trumping pre-emption

    EXAMPLE 3 (Schaffer, 2000):
    According to the law of magic, the 1st spell on a given day will match the enchantment that midnight
    At 12 noon, Merlin casts a spell S1 (the 1st of its kind that day) to turn the prince into a frog
    At 6 pm on the same day, Morgana casts a spell S2 (the only other spell of its kind that day) to turn the prince into a frog
    At 12 midnight, the prince becomes a frog (F)

    Merlin's spell S1 is the trumping cause
    Morgana's spell S2 is the trumped backup cause
    The effect is F (i.e. the prince becoming a frog at 12 midnight)


    Merlin's spell S1 causes F at 12 midnight
    However, there is no counterfactual dependence of F on S1
    Morgana's spell S2, cast at 6 pm, is the dependency-breaking backup cause
    Trumping pre-emption is a special case of redundant causation


    ∴ The counterfactual theory of causation cannot handle cases of pre-emption



    PROBLEM 3: Backtracking counterfactuals




    1. Had F not occurred, C would not have occurred
    2. Had C not occurred, E would not have occurred either
    3. Had F not occurred, E would not have occurred
    4. However, there is no causal relation between E and F

    5. In the actual world @, C temporally precedes F
    6. ∼F ☐⟶ ∼C — Had F not occurred, C would not have occurred
    7. Lewis calls '∼F ☐⟶ ∼C' a backtracking counterfactual: this backtracking counterfactual is problematic

    8. ∴ We need to patch up our counterfactual semantics to more systematically exclude backtracking counterfactuals




    PROBLEM 4: Circularity




    The 4 STEPS in Lewis' counterfactual theory of causation:
    1. STEP 1: Analysis of the truth conditions of counterfactuals in terms of possible and actual worlds (@, w1, w2, etc)
    2. STEP 2: Analysis of counterfactual dependence in terms of counterfactuals
    3. STEP 3: Analysis of causal dependence in terms of counterfactual dependence
    4. STEP 4: Analysis of causation in terms of causal dependence


    1. This theory aims to deliver causal relationships in terms of counterfactual dependence
    2. However, there are cases of counterfactual dependence that are not cases of causal dependence
    3. ∴ It appears that the relevant cases of counterfactual dependence must still be defined in terms of causal relationships
    4. This would result in a circularity of analysis


    EXAMPLE 1 (Counterfactual Dependence without Causal Dependence): Pentagon

    In EXAMPLE 1:
    1. EVENT 1: I draw a figure with five sides.
    2. EVENT 2: I draw a pentagon.
    3. EVENT 2 depends counterfactually on EVENT 1: Had I not drawn a figure with five sides, then I would not have drawn a pentagon
    4. However, EVENT 1 does not cause EVENT 2
    5. Instead, EVENT 1 constitutes EVENT 2


    EXAMPLE 2 (Counterfactual Dependence without Causal Dependence): Law-breaking

    In EXAMPLE 2:
    1. EVENT 1: One commits an act of murder.
    2. EVENT 2: One breaks the law.
    3. EVENT 2 depends counterfactually on EVENT 1: Had one not committed the act of murder, then one would not have broken the law
    4. However, EVENT 1 does not cause EVENT 2
    5. Instead, EVENT 1 constitutes EVENT 2




    PROBLEM 5: No guidelines for establishing degree of causal influence




    Any event that has a small influence on the timing or manner of the effect can be said to be a cause
    However, there is no discussion in the counterfactual theory of causation of the degree to which a cause influences an effect




    Probabilistic Theory of Causation



    Patrick Suppes


    Hans Reichenbach



    Both the regularity theory of causation and the counterfactual theory of causation generally regard causality as a deterministic relationship between events: causes produce their effects without fail

    Conversely, the probabilistic theory of causation maintains the following:
    1. Even with complete knowledge of the world and all the relevant information, the cause does not always produce the effect without fail


    2. According to the probabilistic theory of causation (Reichenbach, 1956, Good, 1961, Suppes, 1970, Eells, 1991):
      1. C is a positive cause of E if C raises the probability of E occurring
      2. X causes prima facie Y iff P(Y|X) > P(Y)

      3. C is a negative cause of E if C lowers the probability of E occurring
      4. X causally inhibits prima facie Y iff P(Y|X) < P(Y)

      5. Otherwise, C is causally neutral w.r.t. E
      6. X is not a prima facie cause (positive or negative) of Y iff P(Y|X) = P(Y)


    The probabilistic theory of causation typically identifies the conditions for prima facie causality and offers different METHODS for distinguishing between causes and non-causes
    1. METHOD 1: Information-based theories
    2. A cause provides some information about the effect that cannot be gained in other ways
    3. METHOD 1 (or one of its appropriate variants) is used to infer causal relationships from observational data


    4. METHOD 2: Manipulation theories
    5. A cause is a means of bringing about an effect
    6. The probability or value of the effect alters when its cause is manipulated
    7. METHOD 2 relies on the manipulation of causes


    8. Neither METHOD 1 nor METHOD 2 subsume each other
    9. In addition, there are counterexamples to both METHOD 1 and METHOD 2



    PROBLEMS with the probabilistic theory of causation


    Problem

    Description



    PROBLEM 1: Probability-altering without Causality





    EXAMPLE:
    Smoking (S) is the common cause of yellow-stained fingers (Y) and lung cancer (L)
    ∴ Possessing yellow-stained fingers (Y) raises the probability of lung cancer (L)
    However, there is no causal relationship between Y and L

    When we hold fixed the common cause S (viz. smoking), we screen off Y and L from each other (Reichenbach, 1956)



    PROBLEM 2: Causality without Probability-altering




    EXAMPLE (Hesslow, 1976, Cartwright, 1989):
    1. The birth control pill (BCP) raises the probability of a blood-clotting chemical (BC) forming
    2. BC raises the probability of thrombosis (T)
    3. At the same time, the birth control pill (BCP) lowers the probability of pregnancy (P)
    4. As P raises the probability of T, BCP also lowers the probability of T
    5. Thrombosis (T) raises the probability of chest pain (CP)
    6. ∴ Multiple paths between pairs of nodes BCP and T can cause path cancellation
    7. ∴ We could have causality without probability-altering




    PROBLEM 3: Determinism




    1. In deterministic cases, an effect E occurs with P(E|C) = 1 as a result of a cause C
    2. In more complex cases, there may be multiple causes C1, C2, …, etc, each of which leads to the effect with a probability P(E|(C1 ∨ C2 ∨ …)) = 1
    3. ∴ Even if C1 had not occurred, E would still have occurred with a probability of 1