• Back to Profile

  • When one particular species of event has always … been conjoined with another,
    we make no longer any scruple of foretelling one upon the appearance of the other,
    and of employing that reasoning, which can alone assure us of any matter of fact or existence.
    We then call the one object, Cause; the other, Effect.
    - David Hume's (1748, §7) An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding

    Granger Causality










    Recall the various philosophical theories of causation:
    The regularity theory of causation — C causes E if every event of type C is followed by an event of type E
    The counterfactual theory of causation — C causes E iff E is causally dependent on C or there is a chain of causal dependence between C and E (analyzed in terms of counterfactual dependence)
    The probabilistic theory of causation — C causes E iff C alters the probability of E

    PROBLEMS with these philosophical theories of causation:
    1. PROBLEM 1: Lack of philosophical consensus about the concept of causality
    2. 'Unlike art, causality is a concept whose definition people know what they do not like but few know what they do like' (Granger, 1980)

    3. PROBLEM 2: Lack of usefulness in philosophical contributions to causality
    4. See Hart & Honoré (1959) for a discussion on the lack of usefulness of the philosophers' contribution to causality

    5. PROBLEM 3: Lack of common usage terms in philosophical discussions about causality
    6. According to Granger (1980, p. 331), philosophers make no attempt to use common usage terms in their discussion

    7. PROBLEM 4: Lack of concern with operational definitions
    8. Philosophers are not constrained to look for operational definitions

    9. Conversely, the primary advantage of the Wiener-Granger causality approach is that it is easy to understand and pragmatic (see Granger, 2007, pp. 290-1, 294)
      For Granger (1980), the ultimate objective is to produce an operational definition of causality

    10. CAVEAT:
    11. There is a difference between Granger causality and the common-sense understanding of the cause-effect relationship (Lin & Bahadori, 2012)
    12. In addition, Granger's definition of Granger causality has been debated in both philosophy (Cartwright, 1989) and economics (Chowdhury, 1987, Jacobs et al, 1979)




    Norbert Wiener


    C. W. J. Granger




    1. According to Wiener (1956, p. 127):
    2. For 2 simultaneously measured signals, if we can predict the 1st signal better by using the past information from the 2nd signal than by using the information without it, then we call the 2nd signal causal to the 1st one


    3. According to Granger (1980, p. 334):
    4. Let A and B denote two time-series variables
    5. A Granger-causes B, if the probability of B conditional on its own history and the history of A (beside the set of available information) does not equal the probability of B conditional on its own history alone


    6. ∴ This statistical approach to causality is known as Wiener-Granger causality, since Granger's work built on ideas from Wiener (1956)

    7. Granger (1969, 1980) developed a statistical method to take two time series and determine whether one is useful for forecasting the other

    8. Time series X Granger-causes time series Y

      Image source: Wikipedia

    9. Granger did not attempt to relate his method to philosophical definitions of causality
    10. Rather, Granger proposed a new definition of Granger causality that is most similar to correlation




    EXAMPLE (Granger, 1980):
    Suppose that X and Y are the only two random variables in the universe
    Suppose further that a strong correlation is observed between X and Y
    Suppose in addition that God (or an acceptable substitute) can confirm that X does not cause Y
    This leaves open the possibility of Y causing X
    ∴ The strong observed correlation between X and Y might lead to the acceptance of the claim that Y causes X




    Formal definition of Granger causality:
    Let Xt and Yt denote two variables that are suspected to be causally related
    Let Ωt denote all the knowledge available in the universe at t
    Xt Granger-causes Yt + 1 iff:
    P(Yn + 1 ∈ A | Ωn) ≠ P(Yn + 1 ∈ A | Ωn − Xn) for some A

    TRANSLATION: In order for causation to occur, the variable Xn(i.e. the values of variable X up to time n) needs to have some unique information about the value that Yn + 1 (i.e. the value of variable Y at time n + 1) will take in the immediate future




    Axioms

    Image source: Eric Sucar




    The axioms of the Wiener-Granger causality approach:
    1. AXIOM 1: The past and the present may cause the future, but the future cannot cause the past
    2. While the truth of AXIOM 1 cannot be tested using the methods discussed by Granger (1980), work by physicists on time-reversibility does not seem to contradict AXIOM 1 (see Overseth (1967))

    3. AXIOM 2: Ωn contains no redundant information, where Ωn denotes all the knowledge available in the universe at n
    4. If some variable Zn is functionally related to one or more other variables in a deterministic fashion, then Zn should be excluded from Ωn
    5. EXAMPLE:
    6. Temperature can be measured hourly at some location in both degrees Fahrenheit (°F) and degrees Centigrade (°C)
    7. There is no point in including both these variables in Ωn

    8. AXIOM 3: All causal relationships remain constant in direction throughout time
    9. While the strength and lag of causal relationships may change, causal laws are not allowed to change from positive strength to zero, or go from zero to negative strength, through time


    10. IMPLICATIONS of AXIOMS 1-3:
    11. IMPLICATION 1:
    12. Feedback loops are not ruled out: if Xn causes Yn + 1 w.r.t. some information set, then this implies no restrictions on whether or not Yn causes causes Xn + 1

    13. IMPLICATION 2:
    14. It is impossible to find a cause for a series that is self-deterministic: that variable is perfectly forecastable from its own past

    15. IMPLICATION 3:
    16. Instantaneous causality: if there is a data collection problem, then both Xt and Yt could have a common cause that is not included in the information set

    17. IMPLICATION 4:
    18. Spurious causation: where Zt is the common cause of both Xt and Yt, there may be a spurious causation of Y by X if the information set is too restricted
    19. The spurious causation of Y by X w.r.t. the information set Jn(X, Y) vanishes when the information set is expanded to include Z




    Tests




    TEST 1: Bivariate Granger test
    1. Only two time-series are included: the cause Yt and the effect Xt
    2. TEST 1 is concerned with whether Y causes X w.r.t. the information set Jn(X, Y) (i.e. the two-variable case) (Pierce & Haugh, 1977)


    TEST 2: Multivariate Granger test
    1. TEST 2 includes other variables in the model of each time series
    2. TEST 2 comes closer to causal inference than the bivariate test



    PROBLEMS with TESTS 1 & 2


    Test

    Problem


    TEST 1 (Bivariate)

    PROBLEM 1: TEST 1 does not capture Granger's original definition of Granger causality
    Ωn (i.e. all the knowledge in the universe available at time n) is multivariate and Yn (i.e. the values taken by the variable Y up to time n) could be multivariate


    PROBLEM 2: TEST 1 cannot distinguish between causal relationships and correlations between effects of a common cause


    TEST 2 (Multivariate)

    PROBLEM 1: Computational complexity
    TEST 2 becomes computationally infeasible with even a moderate number of lags and variables
    Many areas of work involve influence over long periods of time (e.g. epidemiological studies), but these would be prohibitively complex to test



    More generally:

    PROBLEMS with the Wiener-Granger causality approach





    PROBLEM 1: Granger causality ≠ Causality


    The Wiener-Granger causality approach aims to infer relationships between time series
    However, Granger causality is not generally considered to be a definition of causality or a method of its inference



    Image source:https://www.pmcolumn.com/conflict-resolution-strategies/

    PROBLEM 2: Possibility of conflicting conclusions


    There is a plurality of statistical tests (e.g. the Granger direct test, the Sims test, etc) associated with the Wiener-Granger causality approach
    ∴ It is possible to apply two distinct Granger-causality tests T1 and T2 w.r.t. the same dataset and obtain different outcomes
    For instance, T1 could confirm the null hypothesis while T2 might reject the null hypothesis

    This contradicts AXIOM 3, according to which all causal relationships must remain constant in direction throughout time




    PROBLEM 3: Nonlinear causal relationships


    The most popular tests (e.g. General Granger causality test, Sims test, modified Sims test) associated with the Wiener-Granger causality approach were developed to test only for linear dependencies
    ∴ One may mistakenly interpret the failure of a test to reject the null hypothesis as evidence for a lack of causality, when there may in fact be a nonlinear causal relationship




    PROBLEM 4: Sampling frequency


    When the sampling frequency is insufficient, test results may show bidirectional Granger causality, although the real, unidirectional causal relationship exists and can be detected




    PROBLEM 5: Rational expectations


    EXAMPLE:
    Suppose that a company C is able to predict inflation I rationally (e.g. using better information)
    C then makes purchases X whose amount depends on a future rise in prices and storage cost
    ∴ The expected causal relationship would have the opposite direction: It + 1 Granger-causes Xt

    This would violate AXIOM 1, according to which the future cannot cause the past




    PROBLEM 6: Common causes


    EXAMPLE:
    Z is the common cause of Xt + 1 and Yt + 2
    To an observer, it will appear (erroneously) to be the case that Xt + 1 Granger-causes Yt + 2

    The common cause fallacy should be suspected when Granger causality tests indicate bidirectional Granger causality (viz. X → Y and Y → X)



    PROBLEM 7: Indirect causality


    EXAMPLE 1: Direct causality


    EXAMPLE 2: Indirect causality


    Standard tests associated with the Wiener-Granger causality approach only show dependencies present within a time period and will be unable to distinguish between EXAMPLE 1 and EXAMPLE 2

    Table of erroneous conclusions from Granger causality tests (Maziarz, 2015, p. 101)


    The real causal relationship

    X → Y Y → X X ⟷ Y X ∅ Y

    The test result

    X → Y CORRECT Rational expectations (Noble, 1982) Sampling frequency (McCrorie & Chambers, 2006) Spurious causation due to nonlinear data

    Sampling frequency

    Common cause fallacy (Chu et al, 2004)
    Y → X Rational expectations (Noble, 1982) CORRECT Sampling frequency (McCrorie & Chambers, 2006) Spurious causation due to nonlinear data

    Sampling frequency

    Common cause fallacy (Chu et al, 2004)
    X ⟷ Y Sampling frequency Sampling frequency CORRECT Common cause fallacy (Sims, 1977)

    X and Y may be determined by a 3rd variable Z
    X ∅ Y Causal relationship is nonlinear

    Indirect causality (Dufour & Taamouti, 2010)
    Causal relationship is nonlinear

    Indirect causality (Dufour & Taamouti, 2010)
    Time series are non-stationary (Glasure & Lee, 1998) CORRECT

    KEY:
    1. → denotes unidirectional Granger causality
    2. ⟷ denotes bidirectional Granger causality
    3. ∅ denotes no causal relationship





    Uses




    The Wiener-Granger causality approach is the most influential approach to causality in economics (Hoover, 2006)
    Granger causality is now being applied to econometrics, finance (Granger, 2007), neuroscience (Bressler & Seth, 2011, Ding et al, 2006), epidemiology, and physics to model information flow